|
A
Survey of the Mind
Swami
Satyaswarupananda
Amidst
the Gita discourse, when Arjuna confessed his helplessness
in getting to terms with his mind, comparing it to the impossible
task of controlling the winds, he was not just speaking out
the minds of all spiritual aspirants; he could well have been
speaking for the endless stream of thinkers and scientists
whose wits and imaginations have been engaged in cracking
the riddle of the mind. For, just as spiritual aspirants have
always been struggling to master their own minds, philosophers
and empiricists have been trying, with limited success, to
understand the nature of the human mind in intellectual and
scientific terms. The human mind, however, has remained an
enigma. Be that as it may, the range of knowledge and discipline
that has been brought to bear on these investigations has
been truly phenomenal, and even a brief review of some of
these conceptual and empirical efforts can be highly educative.
Early
Philosophical Theories
The
classical Western (1) concept of the mind has been defined
by Rene Descartes’ dualistic view of it as an ‘unextended
and thinking substance’ distinct from the body, a view that
could be traced back to the Socratic and Platonic concept
of the ‘psyche’ (a word traditionally translated as ‘soul’)
as distinct from ‘soma’, or the body. Of course, what Descartes
actually meant by ‘substance’ has remained obscure and this
has been a cause of much confusion in Western thought; but
this position lead to what Gilbert Ryle called, the ‘ghost
in the machine’ view of an immaterial entity called ‘mind’
controlling bodily function. Termed dualist-interactionism,
this theory is also favoured by some neuroscientists who
are convinced about the inadequacy of neural events in explaining
mental phenomena. (2) However, nobody has been able to provide
a plausible explanation as to how a non-material mind could
bring about physical changes in the brain. Monistic viewpoints
of an immaterial mind were also propounded as a reaction to
the rising popularity of materialism. Bishop Berkeley took
an idealistic position and argued that ‘existence is perception’
(esse et percipii), for one is aware of even the socalled
objective world only in terms of the impressions it leaves
on the mind. Bradley insisted that there is only one infinite
Mind, Idea or Experience that comprehends all of existence
within it. Spinoza considered both matter and mind as attributes
of an underlying substance called God or Nature.
In
contrast, almost all mainstream Indian philosophical positions
since ancient times took a materialistic view of the mind
ever since the Sankhyas conceived of a sharp distinction between
the conscious Purusha and the material Prakriti. The latter
(comprised of three basic constituents called gunas3), with
all its evolutes (which include the mind), has been conceived
of as dynamic but devoid of consciousness. The Vedantists
essentially accept this duality, though they discovered a
transcendent unity, of the nature of pure consciousness, in
Brahman. While the Sankhyas considered the mind to be one
of the early evolutes of Prakriti (there being twenty-three
other evolutes), the Vedantists conceived it as composed of
a combination of the sattvic components of the five elements
in their subtle (or tanmatra) form. The Naiyayikas,
or logicians, on the other hand, proposed that the mind was
a distinct material category (at par with eight others, namely
the five elements, time, the directions and the soul).
With
the progress of the Enlightenment, the triumph of the Scientific
and Industrial Revolutions, and the concomitant rise of empiricism
and positivism (which recognized only scientifically established
facts as valid), Western thinkers veered progressively towards
a material explanation of mental phenomena.
Gilbert
Ryle, who was for many years the editor of the reputed philosophical
journal Mind, in his well-recognized and polemical
work Concept of Mind tried to refute the Cartesian
view of the separation of mental and physical existence -
‘the ghost in the machine’ concept. He argued that human nature
differs only in degree from a clockwork and that thought,
imagination, perception, feeling and the like are nothing
but expressions of different physical states (a position termed
reductive materialism) if not, on occasions, simple meaningless
verbiage (eliminative materialism). In his later days,
however, Ryle was more discreet about writing off mental phenomena,
probably realizing that doing so would reduce all his arguments
also to meaningless verbiage; arguments after all are not
physical entities. Although Ryle’s was essentially a linguistic
analysis, his ideas were also boosted by the behavioural school
of psychologists, remarkable advances in neuroanatomy and
neurophysiology, and the early ideas of the exponents of artificial
intelligence.
Early
Experimental Studies
The
first half of the twentieth century saw the behaviourists
describing human behaviour as determined responses to environmental
stimuli. Pavlov demonstrated the classical conditioned response
of involuntary bodily function to a conditioning environmental
stimulus - the famous Pavlovian dog salivating in response
to a bell that was earlier sounded regularly before food.
Skinner and his associates studied the process of operant
conditioning whereby voluntary behaviour is controlled through
rewards and punishments - rats learning to run in a maze or
pigeons pressing a lever for food are typical examples. Behaviourists
like Watson and Skinner were convinced that all observable
human behaviour could be explained in terms of conditioned
learning. Although behaviourism remained very influential
through much of the last century, it is now well recognized
that a great deal of what is distinctively human behaviour
is not simply conditioning but is acquired through cognitive
learning, a process that involves understanding
how a task is accomplished. Comparison of the language used
by chimpanzees and humans illustrates this very well. Although
chimpanzees have been taught to communicate through sign language,
this chimpanzee language has been entirely of the expressive
and signalling variety, totally devoid of abstraction. In
contrast, even a two- or three-year-old human child spontaneously
learns to speak according to the rules of grammar (though
rudimentary to begin with), and uses language for abstract
descriptive and argumentative purposes.
Around
the middle of the last century scientists and clinicians were
also making rapid advances in their understanding of neuronal
and cerebral structure and function. By selectively stimulating
or destroying small portions of the brain, in experimental
animals as well as humans, Penfield, Old, Gazzaniga, Sperry
and others dramatically demonstrated how discrete areas in
the brain subserved distinct sensory, motor or emotional function.
This was the beginning of the idea of a ‘modular’ brain, wherein
the brain was seen as an ensemble of specialized units or
modules, each subserving a specific mental function. Mental
functioning thus became identified with definitive brain activity,
a position upheld by most scientists. Physicists went a step
further and attempted to simulate this activity. Neuroanatomists
had shown that the human nervous system, including the brain,
was essentially a massive mass of extensively interconnected
neurons along which information could flow in the form of
electrical impulses. In 1943, McCulloch and Pitts, in a classic
paper, presented A Logical Calculus of the Idea Immanent
in Nervous Activity, (4) essentially a mathematical algorithm
that could be used by a computer (which were at that time
at a rudimentary state of development) to simulate neural
function. The idea caught on quickly. If the function of one
neuron could be simulated, then so could that of an entire
mass of nerve cells, and thus, essentially of the entire brain.
Subsequently, phenomenal advances in computer technology as
well as neurophysiology have kept alive this idea (termed
artificial intelligence or AI) of man-made machines being
able to simulate human brain function some day.
The
development of rudimentary computers in the first half of
the twentieth century was preceded by the attempt by mathematicians
to work out a set of algorithmic procedures that could be
used to solve any, and every, mathematical problem. This was
the famous Hilbert programme, essentially an attempt to show
that every mathematical problem could be reduced to a finite
series of calculations (and was therefore amenable to computer
simulation). This effort was given a decisive blow by Kurt
Godel through his classical ‘incompleteness theorem’ (formulated
in 1930) which indisputably established that no formal system
of sound mathematical rules of proof can ever suffice, even
in principle, to establish all the true propositions of ordinary
arithmetic. Although the formal proof of this theorem is complicated,
it essentially amounts to showing that even if one managed
to construct a ‘super-algorithm’ that could consistently be
used to check the validity of other mathematical propositions,
it could not logically be used to prove its own validity.
(5)
Tremendous
advances in recent times in computer technology and cybernetics,
however, testify to the fact that the failure of the Hilbert
programme has in no way deterred people in their attempt to
develop AI systems; and they have achieved no mean success.
Cybersystems can handle massive volumes of logical operations
at phenomenal speeds as well as electronically store and retrieve
entire libraries of information as ‘memory’. Modern robotics
has been used to carry out complex operations, and ‘servo-control’
mechanisms have been developed not only to fine-tune robotic
‘intentionality’ but also incorporate ‘experiential learning
behaviour’ in robots. Machines have also been programmed to
sense and respond to apparently subjective issues like human
emotion. A lie-detector is a simple example.
The
Criterion of the ‘Mental’
Despite
these remarkable achievements, no one is willing to grant
machines a ‘mental’ status - all these efforts remain mere
simulations. What, then, characterizes mental activity? While
a lot of phenomena are commonly taken as mental, a strict
defining criterion for mental events has been difficult to
formulate. The subjective nature of mental events - of consciousness,
of ‘raw’ feeling and the privacy of the mental world - has
been recognized. Awareness (including self-awareness), understanding
(or abstract thinking), purposeful or intentional behaviour,
emotional dispositions, and the ability for introspection
and reflexive thinking (knowing that one knows) have all been
proposed as phenomena suggesting the presence of a mind. The
very subjectivity of these effects has made an objective definition
difficult to come by. This, in itself, is an indicator of
something fundamental involved in that consciousness which
typifies mental phenomena, the thing-in-itself in Kantian
terms that remains unknown and unknowable.
Physical
Theories of the Mind
While
the subject-object dichotomy has been taken as an inviolable
principle by many philosophical systems, the empiricists and
positivists - who constitute the dominant philosophical position
in the present scientific community - have either tried to
avoid the issue of subjectivity or tried to wish it away,
naively taking it to be an epiphenomenon or a byproduct of
objective events in the brain. (6) This epiphenomenalism,
as also the more reductive identity theory, which takes
the mind to be simply another description of physical events
in the brain, unfortunately runs into several pragmatic problems.
First, none of the laws of physics or neurobiology has anything
to say about the emergence or existence of consciousness,
which is a fundamental attribute of mental phenomena. Second,
till date, it has not been possible to show that consciousness
emerges spontaneously at a certain level of complexity in
a material system. The recent interest in theories of Chaos,
that is, the study of highly complex and irregular systems
determined effectively by a few initial physical parameters
(for example the behaviour of a complex cyclone, which could
dramatically change with small changes in the weather conditions
at the origin), has failed to provide any meaningful insight
into consciousness, although it is true that the apparently
random train of thoughts emerging from an idle mind could,
technically speaking, be quite accurately described as chaotic.
So to aver that with further advances in the neurosciences,
all mental phenomena, including self-awareness, would be shown
to result from specific brain activity remains wishful thinking.
This position has been termed promissory materialism
by the philosopher of science Karl Popper.
There
have also been dissenting voices from within the scientific
community. One such person is Roger Penrose, a mathematician
and theoretical physicist of renown, who has in recent times
contributed substantially to the understanding of the fundamental
scientific and philosophical issues involved in the working
of the mind. Penrose believes that, as empiricists, scientists
must try to explain mental phenomena in terms of physical
processes - consciousness, after all, manifests itself through
the physical medium of a brain - but he is convinced that
‘any genuine progress in the physical understanding of the
phenomenon of consciousness will also need - as a prerequisite
- a fundamental change in our physical world view. (7) And
how does Penrose view the physical world? ‘We might well ask,’
says he, ‘What is matter according to the best theories that
science has been able to provide? The answer comes back in
the form of mathematics, not so much as a system of equations
(though equations are important too) but as subtle mathematical
concepts that take a long time to grasp properly.’ (8) He
adds, ‘Every one of our conscious brains is woven from subtle,
physical ingredients that somehow enable us to take advantage
of the profound organization of our mathematically underpinned
Universe - so that we, in turn, are capable of some kind of
direct access, through the Platonic quality of “understanding”,
to the very ways in which our universe behaves at many different
levels.’ Penrose is referring here to the world of ‘Absolute
Ideas’ that Plato conceived of as underlying (and, in a way,
of greater permanence than) the perceptual world. He concedes
that some people find it hard to conceive of this Platonic
world as existing on its own - they may think of mathematical
concepts merely as idealizations of our physical world (a
useful tool for understanding it) - but is quick to add:
Now,
this is not how I think of mathematics, nor, I believe,
is it how most mathematicians or mathematical physicists
think about the world. They think about it in a rather different
way, as a structure precisely governed according to timeless
mathematical laws. … One of the remarkable things about
the behaviour of the world is how it seems grounded in mathematics
to a quite extraordinary degree of accuracy. The more we
understand about the physical world, and the deeper we probe
into the laws of nature, the more it seems as though the
physical world almost evaporates and we are left only with
mathematics. The deeper we understand the laws of physics,
the more we are driven into the world of mathematics and
of mathematical concepts. (9)
Anybody
involved deeply in theoretical physics should be able to corroborate
Penrose’s thoughts. Eugene Wigner had also discussed this
issue in a paper titled ‘The Unreasonable Effectiveness of
Mathematics in the Physical Sciences’, written in 1960. The
ability of scientists to arrive at physically valid results
through thought experiments, the high degree of experimental
accuracy of apparently counter-intuitive propositions like
‘warping of the space-time continuum’ as the Einsteinian explanation
of gravity, and the ability to make strong, experimentally
verifiable predictions as a test of validity of any new physical
theory - all suggest a close link between the ‘mental’ and
the ‘physical’ world.
Mathematical
truths, in fact, constitute only one of the Platonic absolutes.
Plato also conceived of Beauty and Goodness as absolute values.
Physiologists tell us that the human brain with its two cerebral
hemispheres often shows a clear distinction between its two
halves - the left hemisphere is involved primarily with logical
operations, as in mathematics, and the right in appreciating
spatio-temporal configurations essential to the aesthetic
sense. Of course, many people have a harmonious blend of these
faculties. Paul Dirac, the famous quantum physicist and Nobel
laureate, was reputed to judge the validity of his mathematical
formulations in terms of their intrinsic aesthetic ‘beauty’.
As regards human ethical values (the correlate of goodness),
however, biologists have, till now, very little to offer in
terms of explanation, although the idea of a conscience or
of dharma has been taken by various civilizations as intrinsic
to human nature. (10)
(To
be continued)
Notes
and References
1.
In an era of globalization the use of the terms Eastern and
Western may appear anachronistic. However, the fact remains
that modern scientific discipline is closely aligned to values
developed in the Western hemisphere, while Yoga and Vedanta
still remain largely identified with Eastern cultures, though
millions of people in the West are actually using it in one
form or other. Also, the world-views espoused by these two
paradigms are very dissimilar in some respects. This article
highlights some of these dissimilarities with the aim of suggesting
a fusion of horizons at a deeper level.
2.
For example see Sir John Eccles and Daniel N Robinson, The
Wonder of Being Human: Our Brain and Our Mind (Boston
and London: Shambhala, 1985).
3.
The three gunas are tamas (inertia), rajas (activity) and
sattva (the principle of equilibrium). In the physical world
tamas and rajas manifest as matter and energy while sattva
mediates consciousness (sattvam laghu prakashakam).
4.
Reprinted in W S McCulloch, Embodiments of Mind (Boston:
MIT Press, 1965) and quoted in Roger Penrose, Shadows of
the Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 352.
5.
See Roger Penrose, The Emperor’s New Mind (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1989), 138-41; also, Swami Atmapriyananda,
‘Vedanta and Mathematical Logic’ in Prabuddha Bharata,
May and June 1999.
6.
Darwin had wondered why thought as a secretion of the brain
should be considered more wonderful than gravity as a property
of matter.
7.
Shadows, 391.
8.
Ibid., 419.
9.
Roger Penrose et al, The Large, the Small, and the Human
Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 2-3.
10.
See Swami Vivekananda, ‘The Real Nature of Man’ in The
Complete Works of Swami Vivekananda, 9 vols. (Calcutta:
Advaita Ashrama, 1-8, 1989; 9, 1997), 2.70-87; also, Swami
Bhajanananda, ‘Why Should We Be Moral?’ in Prabuddha Bharata,
January 1985.
Read
more:
A
Survey of the Mind (August 2004)
A
Survey of the Mind (September 2004)
|