|
Editorial
Bioethics and Cloning
Swami
Satyaswarupananda
The Evolution of Ethics
Ethical
issues have been confronting humans since prehistoric times.
Social life is dependent on internal regulation. Restraint
and reciprocity are unavoidable exigencies of social living.
A pack of wolves will end its internecine fight once one of
them displays submissive behaviour while the same pack tears
apart any other animal that happens to stray into its territory.
In a herd of elephants moving in search of fresh vegetation,
if a calf happens to fall back or stray away, the herd will
return, trace the straggler and take it along. If the latter
happens to have injured itself, it will be nursed and helped
till it can again move with the group. Monkeys helping delouse
each other is not an unfamiliar sight. Crow-watchers would
have come across a court of crows crowing down or pecking
a recalcitrant member into submission. All these acts contain
rudiments of what in humans is highly complex ethical behaviour.
Issues
in ethical philosophy as well as normative and applied ethics
had engaged thinkers in many an ancient civilization. The
concepts of dharma and rita as found in the early Vedic
texts and elaborated later in the Upanishads, Brahmanas, Smritis,
and Puranas comprise the oldest comprehensive philosophy of
ethics. The Ashtanga Magga of Gautama Buddha, the moral
imperatives of the Jaina tirthankaras, the Tao of simple and
wise living, the 'superior-man' of correct behaviour as envisaged
by Confucius, and the moral speculations of the ancient Greek
philosophers - from Pythagoras to Socrates, Plato and Aristotle
- all contain sophisticated ethical concepts that form the
basis of much of modern ethical thought.
The
subsequent centuries saw the growth of two distinct strands
of ethical thinking: one connected with specific religions
- the legalistic traditions of Jewish ethics based on the
Old Testament and Islamic ethics derived from the Quran, the
moral theology of the Christian Church, the acharas
of Sanatana Dharma guided by the Dharmashastras, and so on;
the other strand obtained from the works of free thinkers
in post-Renaissance Europe. The major themes underpinning
ethical discussions undertaken by both these strands have
included the following questions: Why should we be moral?
What is the source of the moral impulse? Is it natural or
prescriptive in origin? Is morality rational or emotive? How
does one decide on what is moral? Is moral judgement subjective
or are there universal and objective elements to it? That
the debate on these issues refuses to die is proof of the
paradoxical nature of normative judgement that often impels
us to derive the 'ought' (what we should do) from the 'is'
(the facts of existence), something that cannot be logically
supported, as David Hume pointed out.
Pragmatism
characterizes modern man, and the post-modern is marked by
ethical relativism. It would therefore appear that abstract
theories of ethics would have little practical relevance in
today's world, and this is not totally untrue. Yet, there
is currently an unprecedented global interest in applied ethics
as is evidenced by the various movements for human (and animal)
rights and civil liberties, the formation of various 'liberation'
groups with their particular philosophies and even theologies,
and the multitude of activists - the pacifists, the environmentalists
and the like - all of whom have agenda with strong ethical
content. In this burgeoning field of applied ethics, bioethics,
dealing with the ethical issues raised by advances in biology
and medicine, stands out for its remarkable growth and the
number of disciplines that it engages. This growth has been
the result of two factors: first, advances in medicine have
brought into focus issues at the limits of life - issues relating
to prolonging life, euthanasia, non-natural means of conception
and abortion, all of which impinge on the sanctity of life,
human dignity, right to life and freedom of choice; second,
advances in genetic technology, including the complete decoding
of the human genome and understanding the biology of embryonic
cells with their potential to form any type of tissue, now
provide us with the ability to tailor the structure and function
of cells, tissues and even entire individuals. This, obviously,
has tremendous moral implications. Cloning is one technological
advancement that exemplifies these issues, and a brief examination
may be worthwhile.
What
is Cloning?
A
group of genetically identical cells comprise a clone. All
our body cells are genetically uniform and are therefore clones
of each other. Organisms reproducing by asexual means like
amoebae, bacteria or hydra also give rise to clones - the
entire organism being a clone of its parent. The plants that
we grow from cuttings in our garden are also clones of the
mother plant. In the 1980s scientists learnt to clone mice
by transferring the nucleus of an embryonic cell into a mouse
ovum from which the nucleus (containing genetic material)
had been removed. This fusion cell, when implanted into the
mouse uterus, started dividing and led to the formation of
a mouse pup with all its genetic material derived from one
parental source. In 1997, Ian Wilmut managed to clone an entire
sheep - the famous Dolly - by this method of 'nuclear transfer'.
What was novel about Wilmut's process was that he obtained
the nucleus from the udder cell of a donor sheep, and udder
cells are terminally differentiated cells, that is, they are
mature tissue cells that were till then thought incapable
of taking part in fresh tissue formation. The chemical environment
of the ovum apparently 'tricked' the genes in the transferred
nucleus into behaving like the genetic material of an embryonic
cell (called a 'pluripotent stem cell' as it can participate
in the formation of all types of tissues). This process, called
'adult somatic cell nuclear transfer', thus led to the formation
of a clone with genetic material derived from a non-reproductive
tissue.
This
type of cloning, called 'reproductive cloning' because it
is used for reproductive purposes, raised a furore among ethicists
who believed that such methods applied to humans can be badly
misused. Popular imagination took this to be 'playing God',
and popular writers warned of the possibility of planned creation
of Frankenstein's monsters; if one Hitler was enough to ravage
the world, what would happen if ten Hitler clones were let
loose! Concerns were also raised about the psychological effects
on the cloned offspring arising from its artificial birth
and its total genetic identity with one parent.
Most
of these speculations do not stand up to scientific scrutiny
for the simple reason that clones are highly unlikely to show
behaviour identical to their parents, for behaviour is heavily
influenced by environmental factors. The growth of the human
brain is markedly influenced by the type of stimulation it
receives in the years after birth and this stimulation keeps
moulding the brain in adult life too. So differences in environmental
factors will themselves ensure against behavioural identity.
Moreover, Hitler was as much a product of history as he was
of his genes and his upbringing; and a simultaneous reproduction
of all these factors can safely be ruled out. Even identical
twins that are natural clones rarely show identical behaviour
despite similar upbringing. Nor has their genetic identity
been found to cause any adverse psychological effect.
Yet
there are hardly any credible scientists who support human
reproductive cloning. This is because the process is not only
very inefficient but also entails considerable risk. The genetic
reprogramming required of the adult nucleus for it to initiate
the formation of the embryo is hardly ever as correct as that
obtained from normal reproductive tissue; so the cloned animals
invariably have some organic defect. Consequently, there is
a well-justified, effective global moratorium on human reproductive
cloning.
The
promise of adult nuclear transfer lies elsewhere, in a process
called 'therapeutic cloning'. If after nuclear transfer the
developing embryonic cells, instead of being implanted into
a womb, are artificially cultured in vitro, they give rise
to a clone of embryonic stem cells instead of a foetus. These
cells can then be chemically induced to transform themselves
into virtually any type of tissue cell which can be reinjected
or transplanted into the original donor to correct various
deficiencies in tissue function like diabetes or Parkinson's
disease. This technology holds out great hope for many incurable
conditions and also the promise of more cost- effective therapies.
The
moral objections to therapeutic cloning are more fundamental.
If human cells and embryos are living entities, can experimentation
with these be morally justified? Also, does not the commercialization
of these tissues and processes violate human dignity? These
questions provide us with an appropriate point of departure
for examining the Vedantic view of human life and biological
development, for it is this understanding that will help us
formulate an answer to these questions.
The
Upanishadic View of Life and Transmigration
An
understanding of the Vedantic view of life is essential to
an appreciation of its ethical viewpoint. Three ideas are
crucial to this understanding: one, individual life, as perceived
by the Upanishads, is only one component in an intricately
interlinked mass of Consciousness that is life; two, our present
existence as living subjects is only one of a series of transmigratory
existences that we have been having since time immemorial;
three, the experiencing and transmigratory subject (jivatman)
is distinct from the physical body derived from genetic material
contributed by parents.
A
description of the process of transmigration is provided by
the Brihadaranyaka Upanishad. Acharya Shankara introduces
the matter in the following words: 'Now the question is, when
the self loaded with knowledge etc., is about to go to another
body, does it leave the old body and go to another, like a
bird going to another tree? [This is the Jaina view.]
Or is it carried by another body serving as a vehicle to the
place where, according to its past work, it is to be born?
[This is the view of the devatavadins.] Or does it
stay here, while its organs become all-pervading and function
as such? [This is the Sankhya view.] Or is it that
so long as it remains in the body, its organs are contracted
to the body's limits, but when it dies they become all-pervading
- like the light of a lamp when the (enclosing) jar is broken
- and contract again when a new body is made? [This is
the Vedantic view.]' (1) The Vedantic view is supported
by Upanishadic texts that explicate the pervasive nature of
the sense organs (in their subtle form) (Brihadaranyaka
Upanishad, 1.5.13) and their contraction to (or identification
with) the limits of specific physical bodies. (Ibid., 1.3.22)
The same Upanishad figuratively illustrates the process of
transmigration with the example of a moving leech: 'Just as
a leech moving on a blade of grass reaches its end, takes
hold of another support, and draws itself together towards
it, so does the self (jivatman) throw this body aside … take
hold of another support, and draw itself together towards
it.' (Ibid., 4.4.3)
This
alternate body, however, is not the gross body that the jivatman
is finally destined to take up. It is a subtle body, predominantly
aqueous, that must first move through several distinct phases
as delineated in the 'panchagni-vidya' sections of the Chandogya
and Brihadaranyaka Upanishads. (Chandogya, 5.3-10
and Brihadaranyaka, 6.2) Three courses are open to
the jivatman: the bright northern course of the gods (devayana)
for those exclusively devoted to meditation; the darker southern
course of the manes (pitriyana) for those who have
led dharmic lives, performed scriptural rituals and engaged
in welfare activities; and the third course for evil-doers
that leads to non-human birth, either directly or after hellish
experiences. The devayana and pitriyana are
characterized by ascent through various states like the solar
and lunar spheres, which are, as Swami Vivekananda explains,
'visions (that) rise in succession before the jiva, who himself
neither goes nor comes'. (2) The descent along pitriyana
is the prototypal descent, marked by identification in succession
with clouds, rain, crops, the man eating these crops, and
finally with a particular woman at the time of conception.
These identities, again, are only abstract concepts and not
gross transformations, as Acharya Shankara has clarified in
his commentary on the Brahma Sutras. (3)
These
concepts may not appear easily intelligible, but they reflect
the fact that Consciousness underpins all existence and can
manifest in specific forms. This Consciousness is not to be
confused with awareness, for the jivatman's identity with
rain, plants, and such other stages in its transmigratory
path are not marked by awareness. (4) Hence the conceptus
in its early embryonic and foetal stages in the mother's womb
is not considered a separate individual. Its individuality
is established only when the jivatman actually 'enters' it
and establishes a psychic identity, for the jivatman is nothing
but the transmigrating psychic apparatus comprising the mind
and related sense organs in their subtle form. According to
the Garbha Upanishad, a text that deals with human
embryonic development, this entry occurs in the seventh month
of foetal life. This was also the time that the foetus was
traditionally considered to take to reach biological viability,
or the ability to survive outside the mother's womb. However,
with advances in medical technology, foetuses delivered several
weeks earlier can now be helped to survive.
This
psychic identity associated with viability establishes the
individuality of the developing baby. It is then subject to
awareness (albeit in rudimentary forms) and the Upanishadic
and Puranic texts cite many instances of remarkably heightened
awareness of the baby in the womb.
It
is important that though viability marks the embodiment of
the jivatman, yet the earlier embryonic stages are not considered
non-living, for the integrity of cellular and tissue structure
is evidence of the presence of active prana (the synonym for
'life'). At this early stage, however, the prana is dependent
on maternal support. (5) This distinction between life and
its supporting Consciousness is indicated by Yajnavalkya during
one of the debates in King Janaka's court when he asks his
interlocutors, 'If a tree, after it is felled, springs forth
anew from its root, from what root does a man spring forth
after being cut down by death?' and then immediately warns,
'Do not say, "From the seed", for that is produced
from a living man.' (6)
Is
Cloning Ethical?
From
the above-mentioned facts it may be deduced that any injury
to the viable foetus is likely to cause psychic injury to
the jivatman and will lead to karmic repercussions. Injury
or loss in the earlier embryonic stages are not likely to
have these effects, yet the presence of prana demands that
even the embryo be treated with respect.
Is
experimentation on embryonic tissue then morally wrong? The
Vedantic answer to this question depends not so much on the
act as on the attitude behind the act. The entire thrust of
the Bhagavadgita is on the importance of attitudes. Devoid
of selfish motives and done with the general good in mind
even apparently injurious actions have no moral repercussions.
Selfish motives can give even seemingly altruistic actions
a morally negative charge.
The
justification for cloning and related issues of bioethical
concern must therefore be sought not in the specifics of these
processes, but in the motives that impel us to choose them.
It is up to the concerned individuals to be clear about their
motives, and for society to exercise control when the motives
of its members go astray.
An
accurate understanding of the scientific facts is, for sure,
necessary to clear misconceptions and prejudices before one
can arrive at a sound ethical judgement; but deeper ethical
issues may prove more intractable.
International
organizations like the UNESCO have been holding wide-ranging
consultations to formulate norms and policies to regulate
biotechnology. Swami Jitatmanandaji's presentation of the
Hindu view of ethics (the concluding portion of which appears
in this issue) was a part of this process. There are also
strict international legal norms (exemplified by the Nuremberg
Code) for conducting biological research. These aim to prevent
a repeat of the unethical and inhuman use of men and women
as subjects of biological research in Nazi Germany. But there
are few instruments to regulate the equitable distribution
of the fruits of research.
Therapeutic
cloning promises a whole range of remedies for presently incurable
conditions. But whether these will be available to the villages
around Mayavati or the bushmen in Africa, and at what cost,
is the big question. A free-market economy allows few ethical
checks on pricing and availability. In societies where welfare
measures are inadequate and budgetary allocations for health
insubstantial (as is the case in India), costly and inappropriate
technologies can prove a big burden.
The
presence of gross socio-economic disparities can, therefore,
often render plain biological views of ethics redundant. In
fact, under such conditions, 'biological arguments can trivialize
ethics and distract our attention from real moral issues:
the ways in which the genetic potential of humans born into
impoverished environments today is stunted and thwarted'.
As Leon Eisenberg of Harvard Medical School has rightly observed,
'had we the moral commitment to provide every child with what
we desire for our own, what a flowering of humankind there
would be.'
References
1. Shankaracharya's commentary on Brihadaranyaka Upanishad,
4.4.3.
2. The Complete Works of Swami Vivekananda, 9 vols.
(Calcutta: Advaita Ashrama, 1-8, 1989; 9, 1997), 103.
3. Shankaracharya's commentary on Brahma Sutras,
3.1.22.
4. Brahma Sutras, 3.1.24.
5. Aitareya Upanishad 2.1.2.
6. Brihadaranyaka Upanishad, 3.9.28.4-5.
|